Many laws that restrict freedoms are effectively substitutes for private contracts. In a frictionless world we wouldn’t need those laws because every subset of individuals could sign private contracts to decide efficiently what the laws decide bluntly and uniformly. But given transaction costs and bargaining inefficiencies those blunt laws are the best we can do.
Some people might want to sign contracts that constrain themselves. For example I might know that I am tempted to drink too many Big Gulps and I might want to contract with every potential supplier of large sugary drinks, getting them to agree never to sell them to me even if I ask for it. But this kind of contract is plagued not only by the transaction costs and bargaining inefficiencies that justify many existing planks in the social contract, but in addition a new friction: these contracts are simply not enforceable.
Because even with such a contract in place, when I actually am tempted to buy a Slurpee, it will be in the interest of both me and my Slurpee supplier to nullify the contract. (It doesn’t solve the problem to structure the contract so that I have to pay 7-11 if I buy a Slurpee from them. If that contract works then I don’t buy the Slurpee and 7-11 would be willing to agree to sign a second contract that nullifies the first one in order to sell me a Slurpee.)
These considerations alone don’t imply that it would be socially efficient to substitute a blanket ban on large sugary drinks for the unenforceable contracts. But what they do imply is that it would be efficient for the courts to recognize such a ban if a large enough segment of the population wants it. (And this is no way intended to suggest that one Michael Bloomberg by himself constitutes a large enough segment of the population.)
6 comments
Comments feed for this article
March 13, 2013 at 4:18 am
Sune Kristian Jakobsen
If you can make contracts, that can’t be nullified by later contracts, there is a solution: You make a contract with 7-11 that they are not allowed to take money for Slurpees, but they don’t have to give you any. Now they would not sell you any Slurpees, because if they did, you could get your money back afterwards.
March 13, 2013 at 4:24 am
Economie comportementale et bien-être | Rationalité Limitée
[…] Comme le laisse entendre Jeff Ely, taxer les sodas, ou interdire leur vente dans un volume supérieur à une certaine limite comme a voulu le faire le maire de New York, pourrait se justifier par ce raisonnement. Sauf qu’en réalité les circonstances sont un peu différentes. Est-on sûr que les personnes qui consomment les sodas et que celles qui demandent la régulation de leur consommation sont les mêmes personnes ? Dans le cas d’espèce, on peut fortement en douter. Supposons que ce ne soit pas le cas. Nous nous retrouvons alors dans la configuration du premier paragraphe, avec deux populations N et M bien distinctes. Il y a toutefois une différence notable : il est très difficile de considérer que la consommation de S par N génère des externalités négatives sur M. Autrement dit, puisqu’il n’y a pas d’externalité, la situation actuelle (caractérisée par un certain niveau q de consommation par N) est d’ores et déjà optimale au sens de Pareto. L’intervention du législateur ou du politique ne peut alors se justifier que de deux manières : […]
March 13, 2013 at 10:21 am
Enrique
A great example of Schelling’s “credible committment” problem … also, notice that laws are also subject to this problem … that is, even a blunt instrument like a law can be repealed by a future legislature
March 15, 2013 at 9:44 am
Behavioral Economics And The Social Contract | Cheap Talk | Fifth Estate
[…] See full story on cheaptalk.org […]
March 15, 2013 at 11:58 am
Wonks Anonymous
I think these laws are targeted at people who have no inclination of making such a private contract, and that “frictions” have nothing to do with it. The best predictor regarding whether someone favors anti-smoking laws is whether or not they are a smoker themself, with smokers being the most opposed. I think the constituency for these food laws are people who DON’T prefer these kinds of foods.
March 16, 2013 at 12:59 am
Indro
Along Wonks Anonymous’ comment, there is also the externality issue imposed on the society, as well. Society does not like smoking, for instance, because it imposes healthcare costs on the society, passive smoking issues, plus the loss to the family and other people around from the smoker’s ill health and possible death. That’s a great idea for a paper — “Your freedom ends where my freedom begins.”