There is a stockpile of bottled water over here and a bunch of thirsty people over there. What should be done?
Before you can answer that question you first have to figure out what is possible. Don’t think yet about what institution or economic system you are going to use to bring about the outcome, first just ask what is feasible in principle.
There are two choices to make. First, which consumers will get water bottles (the allocation). And second, how much money will be transferred from the consumers to the suppliers (the transfers).
The welfare associated with any choice can be summarized by a pair of numbers: the total utility or surplus of consumers and the surplus of producers. You can plot the set of all such pairs that can be generated by some choice of allocation and transfers on a graph where consumer surplus is on one axis and producer surplus is on the other.
We are really interested in the Pareto efficient choices: the ones on the frontier of the feasible set. In our problem the frontier is a line with slope negative 1. Here’s how you achieve these points. First you allocate all of the water bottles to those consumers who value them the most. This achieves the maximum total surplus. Then you specify transfers in order to distribute this surplus in various ways between suppliers and consumers. As you vary the transfers you move along the frontier swapping producer for consumer surplus dollar for dollar.
Now that you have the feasible set you ask yourself what your social welfare function is. That is, how do you compare different points on the graph? You are essentially saying how you evaluate tradeoffs which reduce the utility of one individual and raise the utility of another. Once you have settled on a standard you choose the best point from the frontier according to that standard.
Then you start asking what economic system you can use to achieve it.
The price system is one. But the price system has a big problem. When water bottles are allocated by setting a price the two dimensions in your graph collapse into one. For example, if you want to achieve the surplus maximizing allocation with a price you are forced to accept one particular division of that surplus. There is a market clearing price p and every consumer who gets a bottle of water pays p to a supplier.
Another way of saying this is that market clearing prices correspond to one single point on your frontier. Is it the point you wanted before you started considering the price system as a mechanism? That would be quite an accident. And barring such a coincidence you are now left asking what else could be done within the confines of the price system?
You can choose a price different from the market clearing price. As you vary the price you do two things. First, you worsen the allocation and as a result total surplus goes down. So you move inside the old frontier. That’s bad. Second, you change the division of surplus. This traces out a new frontier giving you more than one choice. That’s good.
Now you can consult your social welfare function again and ask which point on the price-system-generated frontier do you like the best. Will it be the point corresponding to market-clearing prices? Of course it depends on your social welfare function but again it would be quite a coincidence.
For example it could be that market-clearing prices are very high and give almost all surplus to producers and leave consumers with close to zero surplus. If your social welfare function has diminishing marginal rate of substitution of one individual’s utility for another (whether they are consumers or producers, it doesn’t really matter) you will prefer a more interior point which would be achieved by setting prices below market-clearing levels. You are essentially willing to reduce total surplus by a bit (due to misallocation) in order to achieve a better distribution.
Thus, my response to Erik Brynjolffson, who writes in the comments to my post on price gouging:
Producers also are people, just like consumers, and we’d like to see their utility increased, ceteris paribus. Thus, even if production decisions don’t change, I don’t follow your argument that we should put zero weight on producer surplus.
is that nowhen did I say that we should do that and it’s not part of the argument. Instead the argument is that as long as you don’t think we should always be indifferent to arbitrarily reducing the surplus of one party in favor of another (again regardless of who is a consumer or a supplier) then your optimal price will not be the market-clearing price.
Let me emphasize that this is a very special problem because the quantity of water bottles was given, we don’t have to worry about incentives to produce. Another effect of the price system is to provide those incentives. And when supply is elastic, distorting prices reduces welfare for another reason: the quantity is distorted. The point I am making applies in the special cases when this distortion is small. For example when supply lines are cut in a natural disaster.
Other commenters, like Tyler Cowen, argue that supply cannot be considered perfectly inelastic even in rare, unexpected natural disasters. That’s true, but this is not a limiting argument. It doesn’t require perfectly inelastic supply. The tradeoff is still there with highly, but not perfectly, inelastic supply.
17 comments
Comments feed for this article
October 31, 2012 at 2:03 am
Anonymous
VCG 101 well explained.
October 31, 2012 at 7:58 am
Mike
Wait a minute. What happened to the second-welfare theorem?
October 31, 2012 at 8:29 am
jeff
You mean the result that says any Pareto efficient allocation can be achieved with a price system *provided the social planner can re-distribute endowments in arbitrary ways before markets open*?
November 6, 2012 at 8:19 am
gappy
I see that Jeff answered with a snarky comment to the inquiry about the second th. of welfare Economics. Snarky, because it implies that the Social Planner cannot redistribute endowments. And why not? It happens all the time in the form of rebates, subsidies and tax deductions. It’s not impractical.
November 6, 2012 at 10:10 am
jeff
Gappy, your snark-dar is good, but could use a little calibration. My snarky point was that the second welfare theorem indeed brings back the second dimension but I doubt that you want to use this as an argument in favor of price gouging.
Because in this little economy, redistributing endowments basically means confiscating the water bottles and handing them out to people who want them. I.e. rationing.
The SWT also assumes that the planner already knows who wants them the most. In that world we don’t need a price system. We have a perfectly efficient command economy.
October 31, 2012 at 9:33 am
alex
Very interesting post indeed. Bulow and Klemperer have a recent JPE paper that shows in particular that rationing will hurt consumers under some “standard” conditions (e.g. constant elasticity of demand). See : http://www.voxeu.org/article/new-way-understand-consumer-surplus for a non-(too) technical summary.
October 31, 2012 at 9:44 am
Chris
I don’t understand why we don’t have to worry about incentives to produce. This is not a one time game. There have been disasters before, and there will be disasters in the future. If we fix prices artificially low, that could discourage producers from developing better pre- and post-disaster plans.
Under this condition you may still prefer a below market-clearing price, on distribution grounds, but it will be higher than if you completely disregard the dynamic aspects of the system.
October 31, 2012 at 5:53 pm
Patrick R. Sullivan
‘There is a stockpile of bottled water over here….’
You’ve assumed a can opener.
October 31, 2012 at 6:16 pm
Kaleberg
The goal of the producer is to maximize their power over the consumer. At least that’s what you see if you watch actual producers. This power can then be converted to economic advantage, so the producer should set the price high enough so that only some consumers will be able to buy water and the rest die of thirst as an example to the others. This means that on the next round, the consumers will pay even higher prices, and if there are fewer consumers, that is of no concern to the producer.
October 31, 2012 at 8:03 pm
Fmb
2 thoughts:
1. Sometimes there is no well-defined clearing price. What does a prompt Heimlich maneuver go for when only one person is available to perform it?
2. In any given moment, a consumer can be somewhat close to that kind of situation (flat tire, funeral, very thirsty) and a lot of surplus is lost if they take defensive measures against possible gouging. Essentially there is elasticity of repeat demand.
Sure, roadside repair and funeral parlors solves this with posted prices (the latter by law), but repeat business and reputation have their limits in extreme scenarios.
I’m not saying politicians balance this ideally, but they are appealing to an intuition that is not meritless.
November 8, 2012 at 4:20 am
News Wire | Links for 10-31-2012
[…] The Price Mechanism – Cheap Talk […]
November 8, 2012 at 10:42 am
Hurricane Sandy’s Lesson on Preserving Capitalism « Nuance news
[…] in the wake of Hurricane Sandy, the usual post-disaster debate over the economics and ethics of price-gouging is underway. However, while the question of whether it is okay, even desirable, for businesses to raise prices […]
November 8, 2012 at 11:46 am
Price Gouging « azmytheconomics
[…] Supply? Some have argued that in a disaster, the supply is inelastic and so the price mechanism does not increase supply to […]
November 10, 2012 at 3:30 am
Hurricane Sandy’s Lesson on Preserving Capitalism | FavStocks
[…] of Hurricane Sandy, the usual post-disaster debate over the economics and ethics of price-gouging is underway. However, while the question of whether it is okay, even desirable, for businesses to raise […]
November 12, 2012 at 4:57 am
News Wire | Hurricane Sandy’s Lesson on Preserving Capitalism
[…] of Hurricane Sandy, the usual post-disaster debate over the economics and ethics of price-gouging is underway. However, while the question of whether it is okay, even desirable, for businesses to raise […]
July 13, 2017 at 4:51 pm
マーク・ソーマ 「資本主義を守り抜くには価格システムへの『公平感』を保つことが必要だ ~災害時の『便乗値上げ』の是非を巡る議論から得られる教訓~」(2012年11月28日) — 経済学101
[…] ガソリンスタンドの前にできた長蛇の列。ハリケーン・サンディの直撃を受けてガソリンをはじめとした生活物資の数々が品不足の状態にあり、被災民たちは不安な日々を余儀なくされている。自然災害に見舞われた直後には「便乗値上げ」の是非を巡って経済学的および倫理的な観点から議論が巻き起こるものだが、今回もその例外ではない。自然災害に見舞われた直後に売り手が品物の値段を吊り上げるのは許される行為なのか? 望ましい行為と言えるのか? こういった疑問は確かに重要だ。しかしながら、「便乗値上げ」を巡る議論からはその是非にとどまらない更なる教訓も引き出せると思われるのだ。 […]
April 9, 2020 at 5:04 am
マーク・ソーマ 「資本主義を守り抜くには価格システムへの『公平感』を保つことが必要だ ~災害時の『便乗値上げ』の是非を巡る議論から得られる教訓~」(2012年11月28日) — 経済学101
[…] ガソリンスタンドの前にできた長蛇の列。ハリケーン・サンディの直撃を受けて、ガソリンをはじめとした生活物資の数々が品不足の状態にあり、被災民たちは不安な日々を余儀なくされている。自然災害に見舞われた直後には、「便乗値上げ」の是非を巡って経済学的および倫理的な観点から議論が巻き起こるものだが、今回もその例外ではない。自然災害に見舞われた直後に売り手が品物の値段を吊り上げるのは許される行為なのか? 望ましい行為と言えるのか? こういった疑問は確かに重要だ。しかしながら、「便乗値上げ」を巡る議論からは、その是非にとどまらない更なる教訓も引き出せると思われるのだ。 […]